The cytoarchitectural organization of vertebrate brains can differ markedly across species, and this divergence is most striking in the telencephalon. In mammals, the telencephalon harbors the neocortex, a 6-layered sheet of neurons and other cell types thought to be largely responsible for mammalian cognitive abilities. The nonmammalian telencephala, in contrast, comprise a range of divergent tissue architectures that do not morphologically resemble the neocortex at all. Many neuroanatomists, including myself [Briscoe and Ragsdale, 2018a], have sought to understand the evolutionary relationships of telencephalic structures in order to explain the evolutionary history of the neocortex and, by extension, the origins of human cognitive faculties [Striedter, 1997; Aboitiz and Montiel, 2007; Butler et al., 2011; Bruce, 2012; Jarvis et al., 2013; Suzuki and Hirata, 2013; Dugas-Ford and Ragsdale, 2015; Puelles et al., 2017]. However, and as a result of the conceptual problems inherent in comparing very different biological characters, the history of comparative telencephalon anatomy has been a veritable circus of conflicting ideas [Striedter, 1997]. In this short essay, I aim to eliminate one of them.

Field homology has emerged as a framework for describing the evolution of vertebrate brains, and it is based upon the proposed developmental origins of neuroanatomical characters within the embryo [Nieuwenhuys and Puelles, 2016]. In this view, the developing nervous system is regionalized into a grid-like series of territories, or developmental fields, along anteroposterior and mediolateral coordinates. The fate of adult structures is specified within these fields by conserved transcription factor codes, and each developmental field then gives rise to a specific set of derivatives. As the most crucial claim, if it can be demonstrated that 2 or more vertebrates share a homologous developmental field, then the products of that field in each species are considered to be homologous “as a field” [Puelles and Medina, 2002]. The potential for homology of two compared brain regions – whether they are the same thing – is therefore determined solely by whether they arise from equivalent positions in a shared developmental Bauplan [Nieuwenhuys and Puelles, 2016].

This interpretation of homology is deeply problematic, and its continued application represents a conceptual impediment to future progress in comparative neuroscience. In particular, field homology (1) does not describe either the similarity or common ancestry of compared characters, (2) conflates the independent hierarchical levels of homology, and (3) provides no opportunity for insights into the mechanisms of brain structural evolution. It is, in short, meaningless [Northcutt, 1999].

Homology, as conceived by most comparative biologists, refers to similarity due to common ancestry [Patterson, 1988; Hall, 1994]. Homology refers to similarity, and this component of the definition is essential for a meaningful and practical homology concept. The existence of similarities among organisms – the observation that living things resemble each other and are not instead completely different – itself provides the evidence for the common descent of life and the things it is made of. When we compare two extant species and seek homologies, we are searching for those shared similarities present in their last common ancestor and preserved in their respective lineages. The dissimilarities, or the species-specific properties acquired only after divergence, cannot be considered homologous because they were not present in the last common ancestor.

Field homology differs substantially from this version of homology. Field homology states that neuroanatomical characters are homologous if they arise from equivalent developmental fields, but both similarity and common ancestry are conspicuously absent from the definition. Even if a particular developmental field is conserved in two species, the adult derivatives of that field may not be, especially in the telencephalon. Field homology can therefore be used erroneously to define evolutionarily unrelated, species-specific characters as homologs by lumping similarities and dissimilarities indiscriminately together. To deal with this problem, some authors have argued that homology, or “true sameness,” does not require similarity at all [Puelles and Medina, 2002; Puelles and Ferran, 2012]. This idea is a clear expression of essentialism, a doctrine that the identity and homology of two characters depends upon some essence that transcends their actual physical properties. Consequently, field homology cannot be expected to convey any information about a character beyond the relative location of its progenitors.

Every biological character must have an origin and can be said to exist only within one particular clade: the clade descended from the first species to possess that character. To state that a character has a homolog outside of that clade is to push the origin of that character inappropriately far back into evolutionary time, to a more remote common ancestor where it was not present. The field homology concept enables such an infinite evolutionary regress: if similarity is immaterial to homology, then there is no basis for judging which species possess a character of interest and no means to infer when that character arose or when it has been lost. The line that separates when a character exists, and when it does not, disappears. It has been suggested, for example, that all vertebrate embryos possess exactly the same set of developmental fields in an invariant organizational Bauplan [Albuixech-Crespo et al., 2017]. The rather alarming implication is that every part of the nervous system in every vertebrate can be said to possess a homolog in every other vertebrate, that everything was present since the beginning of the vertebrates or earlier, and that there can be nothing new in brain evolution. A homology concept that generates such extreme conclusions provides little descriptive or explanatory value to comparative neuroanatomy.

Some proponents of field homology hold that “similarity of connections is irrelevant with regard to homology” [Puelles et al., 2017]. This assertion is unequivocally false – connections are either homologous or they are not, and to state that they are irrelevant is to simply avoid the question of their origins. We can test whether neuronal connections are homologous through the same means by which we would test homology of any other compared characters at any level of organization: by assessing their degree of similarity and by determining their phylogenetic distributions [Patterson, 1988; Striedter and Northcutt, 1991; Briscoe et al., 2018]. In other words, it is possible to infer the phylogenetic origins of a connectional trait through comparative analyses. More importantly, the recognition of homology versus non-homology at the level of neuronal circuitry is essential for any mechanistic explanation of brain structural evolution. That is, to understand the evolution of a neuroanatomical structure, we must understand the evolution of its components.

Birds and nonavian reptiles do not possess a neocortex, but their telencephala do contain several classes of excitatory neuronal cell types that are remarkably similar to mammalian neocortical neurons in terms of their connectivity patterns [Briscoe et al., 2018; Briscoe and Ragsdale, 2018b]. Rather than being stacked into a 6-layered cortical structure, these avian and reptilian neuronal cell types are generally organized into clustered nuclei within a structure called the dorsal ventricular ridge. Put simply, what differs across mammalian, avian, and reptilian telencephala is the spatial distribution of their neuronal cell types and circuitry. Thus, an explanation for the origins of the neocortex and of the dorsal ventricular ridge is one that accounts for the origins of their component neuronal cell types and the developmental mechanisms that arrange them differentially. I elaborated upon a hypothesis, initially proposed by Karten [1969], that the similarities seen at the level of neuronal cell types reflect homology due to common descent: the neocortical neuronal cell types are ancestral to amniotes, and the neocortex originated in stem mammals through the developmental reorganization of these preexisting cell types [Briscoe and Ragsdale, 2018a]. The field homology concept, by ignoring homologies at all levels besides developmental fields, is fundamentally inadequate for providing such explanations for evolution at the levels of neuroanatomical structures or neuronal cell types.

It is possible to identify homologous neuroanatomical characters and then to ask whether they are also developmentally specified through conserved patterning mechanisms [Briscoe and Ragsdale, 2018a]. It is even possible to identify homologous developmental patterning mechanisms and to ask whether these give rise to homologous neuroanatomical characters [Pani et al., 2012]. Such questions address homologies at separate and evolutionarily independent levels of biological organization. Homology at the level of progenitor domains cannot be considered a sufficient condition for the homology of adult derivatives, as this would uncouple the homology concept from evolutionary relatedness and render it descriptively meaningless. Field homology, as defined in the references described here, must be rejected in favor of a hierarchical model of evolution.

I thank C. Ragsdale and G. Striedter for comments. I am grateful for postdoctoral funding provided by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation and by the Euro-pean Molecular Biology Organization (EMBO, ALTF 1014–2018).

The author declares no conflicts of interest.

1.
Aboitiz
F
,
Montiel
J
.
Origin and evolution of the vertebrate telencephalon, with special reference to the mammalian neocortex
.
Adv Anat Embryol Cell Biol
.
2007
;
193
:
1
112
.
[PubMed]
0301-5556
2.
Albuixech-Crespo
B
,
López-Blanch
L
,
Burguera
D
,
Maeso
I
,
Sánchez-Arrones
L
,
Moreno-Bravo
JA
, et al
Molecular regionalization of the developing amphioxus neural tube challenges major partitions of the vertebrate brain
.
PLoS Biol
.
2017
Apr
;
15
(
4
):
e2001573
.
[PubMed]
1544-9173
3.
Briscoe
SD
,
Albertin
CB
,
Rowell
JJ
,
Ragsdale
CW
.
Neocortical association cell types in the forebrain of birds and alligators
.
Curr Biol
.
2018
Mar
;
28
(
5
):
686
696.e6
.
[PubMed]
0960-9822
4.
Briscoe
SD
,
Ragsdale
CW
.
Homology, neocortex, and the evolution of developmental mechanisms
.
Science
.
2018
a
Oct
;
362
(
6411
):
190
3
.
[PubMed]
0036-8075
5.
Briscoe
SD
,
Ragsdale
CW
.
Molecular anatomy of the alligator dorsal telencephalon
.
J Comp Neurol
.
2018
b
Jul
;
526
(
10
):
1613
46
.
[PubMed]
0021-9967
6.
Bruce
LL
.
The puzzle of forebrain evolution
.
Brain Behav Evol
.
2012
;
79
(
3
):
141
3
.
[PubMed]
1421-9743
7.
Butler
AB
,
Reiner
A
,
Karten
HJ
.
Evolution of the amniote pallium and the origins of mammalian neocortex
.
Ann N Y Acad Sci
.
2011
Apr
;
1225
(
1
):
14
27
.
[PubMed]
0077-8923
8.
Dugas-Ford
J
,
Ragsdale
CW
.
Levels of homology and the problem of neocortex
.
Annu Rev Neurosci
.
2015
Jul
;
38
(
1
):
351
68
.
[PubMed]
0147-006X
9.
Hall
BK
.
Homology: the hierarchical basis of comparative biology
.
San Diego
:
Academic Press
;
1994
.
10.
Jarvis
ED
,
Yu
J
,
Rivas
MV
,
Horita
H
,
Feenders
G
,
Whitney
O
, et al
Global view of the functional molecular organization of the avian cerebrum: mirror images and functional columns
.
J Comp Neurol
.
2013
Nov
;
521
(
16
):
3614
65
.
[PubMed]
0021-9967
11.
Karten
HJ
.
The organization of the avian telencephalon and some speculations on the phylogeny of the amniote telencephalon
.
Ann N Y Acad Sci
.
1969
;
167
(
1
):
164
79
.
[PubMed]
0077-8923
12.
Nieuwenhuys
R
,
Puelles
L
.
Towards a new neuromorphology
. 1st ed.
Basel
:
Springer International Publishing
;
2016
.
13.
Northcutt
RG
.
Field homology: a meaningless concept
.
Eur J Morphol
.
1999
Apr
;
37
(
2-3
):
95
9
.
[PubMed]
0924-3860
14.
Pani
AM
,
Mullarkey
EE
,
Aronowicz
J
,
Assimacopoulos
S
,
Grove
EA
,
Lowe
CJ
.
Ancient deuterostome origins of vertebrate brain signalling centres
.
Nature
.
2012
Mar
;
483
(
7389
):
289
94
.
[PubMed]
0028-0836
15.
Patterson
C
.
Homology in classical and molecular biology
.
Mol Biol Evol
.
1988
Nov
;
5
(
6
):
603
25
.
[PubMed]
0737-4038
16.
Puelles
L
,
Ferran
JL
.
Concept of neural genoarchitecture and its genomic fundament
.
Front Neuroanat
.
2012
Nov
;
6
:
47
.
[PubMed]
1662-5129
17.
Puelles
L
,
Medina
L
.
Field homology as a way to reconcile genetic and developmental variability with adult homology
.
Brain Res Bull
.
2002
Feb-Mar
;
57
(
3-4
):
243
55
.
[PubMed]
0361-9230
18.
Puelles
L
,
Sandoval
J
,
Ayad
A
,
del Corral
R
,
Alonso
A
,
Ferran
J
, et al
 The pallium in reptiles and birds in the light of the updated tetrapartite pallium model. In:
Striedter
G
, editor
.
Evolution of nervous systems
.
Volume 1
. 2nd ed.
San Diego
:
AcademicPress/Elsevier
;
2017
. pp.
519
55
.
19.
Striedter
GF
.
The telencephalon of tetrapods in evolution
.
Brain Behav Evol
.
1997
;
49
(
4
):
179
213
.
[PubMed]
0006-8977
20.
Striedter
GF
,
Northcutt
RG
.
Biological hierarchies and the concept of homology
.
Brain Behav Evol
.
1991
;
38
(
4-5
):
177
89
.
[PubMed]
0006-8977
21.
Suzuki
IK
,
Hirata
T
.
Neocortical neurogenesis is not really “neo”: a new evolutionary model derived from a comparative study of chick pallial development
.
Dev Growth Differ
.
2013
Jan
;
55
(
1
):
173
87
.
[PubMed]
0012-1592

The author won the “Thomas Karger Award for Excellence in Evolutionary Neuroscience.” The award was presented at the 2018 J.B. Johnston Club Meeting on November 1, 2018.

Copyright / Drug Dosage / Disclaimer
Copyright: All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be translated into other languages, reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, microcopying, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher.
Drug Dosage: The authors and the publisher have exerted every effort to ensure that drug selection and dosage set forth in this text are in accord with current recommendations and practice at the time of publication. However, in view of ongoing research, changes in government regulations, and the constant flow of information relating to drug therapy and drug reactions, the reader is urged to check the package insert for each drug for any changes in indications and dosage and for added warnings and precautions. This is particularly important when the recommended agent is a new and/or infrequently employed drug.
Disclaimer: The statements, opinions and data contained in this publication are solely those of the individual authors and contributors and not of the publishers and the editor(s). The appearance of advertisements or/and product references in the publication is not a warranty, endorsement, or approval of the products or services advertised or of their effectiveness, quality or safety. The publisher and the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to persons or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content or advertisements.